Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Principia Mathematica
- 1. History of Principia Mathematica
- 2. Significance of Principia Mathematica
- 3. Contents of Principia Mathematica
- Bibliography
- Academic Tools
- Other Internet Resources
- Related Entries
1. History of Principia Mathematica
As for the mathematical problems, Whitehead invented most of the notation, except in so far as it was taken over from Peano; I did most of the work concerned with series and Whitehead did most of the rest. But this only applies to first drafts. Every part was done three times over. When one of us had produced a first draft, he would send it to the other, who would usually modify it considerably. After which, the one who had made the first draft would put it into final form. There is hardly a line in all the three volumes which is not a joint product. (1959, 74)
2. Significance of Principia Mathematica
self-evidence is never more than a part of the reason for accepting an axiom, and is never indispensable. The reason for accepting an axiom, as for accepting any other proposition, is always largely inductive, namely that many propositions which are nearly indubitable can be deduced from it, and that no equally plausible way is known by which these propositions could be true if the axiom were false, and nothing which is probably false can be deduced from it. If the axiom is apparently self-evident, that only means, practically, that it is nearly indubitable; for things have been thought to be self-evident and have yet turned out to be false. And if the axiom itself is nearly indubitable, that merely adds to the inductive evidence derived from the fact that its consequences are nearly indubitable: it does not provide new evidence of a radically different kind. Infallibility is never attainable, and therefore some element of doubt should always attach to every axiom and to all its consequences. In formal logic, the element of doubt is less than in most sciences, but it is not absent, as appears from the fact that the paradoxes followed from premisses which were not previously known to require limitations. (1910, 2nd edn 59)
Both Whitehead and I were disappointed that Principia Mathematica was only viewed from a philosophical standpoint. People were interested in what was said about the contradictions and in the question whether ordinary mathematics had been validly deduced from purely logical premisses, but they were not interested in the mathematical techniques developed in the course of the work. ... Even those who were working on exactly the same subjects did not think it worth while to find out what Principia Mathematica had to say on them. I will give two illustrations: Mathematische Annalenpublished about ten years after the publication of Principia a long article giving some of the results which (unknown to the author) we had worked out in Part IV of our book. This article fell into certain inaccuracies which we had avoided, but contained nothing valid which we had not already published. The author was obviously totally unaware that he had been anticipated. The second example occurred when I was a colleague of Reichenbach at the University of California. He told me that he had invented an extension of mathematical induction which he called 'transfinite induction'. I told him that this subject was fully treated in the third volume of the Principia. When I saw him a week later, he told me that he had verified this. (1959, 86)
The first indication that something was seriously wrong appeared in Gödel's well known essay of 1944, “Russell's Mathematical Logic.” There, Gödel points out that line (3) of the demonstration of Russell's proposition *89.16 is an elementary logical blunder, while the crucial *89.12 also appears to be highly questionable. It still remained to be seen whether anything of Russell's proof could be salvaged, in spite of the errors, but John Myhill provided strong evidence of a negative verdict by providing a model-theoretic proof in 1974 that no such proof as Russell's can be given in the ramified theory of types without the axiom of reducibility. (Urquhart 2012)
3. Contents of Principia Mathematica
- Title page of the first edition of Principia Mathematica, Volume 1 (1910)
- Cover of the first paperback issue of Principia Mathematica to *56 (1962).
- “Preliminary Explanations of Ideas and Notations,”
- “The Theory of Logical Types,” and
- “Incomplete Symbols.”
- “The Theory of Deduction,”
- “Theory of Apparent Variables,”
- “Classes and Relations,”
- “Logic of Relations,” and
- “Products and Sums of Classes”,
- “Unit Classes and Couples,”
- “Sub-Classes, Sub-Relations, and Relative Types,”
- “One-Many, Many-One and One-One Relations,”
- “Selections,” and
- “Inductive Relations.”
- “Definition and Logical Properties of Cardinal Numbers,”
- “Addition, Multiplication and Exponentiation,” and
- “Finite and Infinite”.
- “Ordinal Similarity and Relation-Numbers,”
- “Addition of Relations, and the Product of Two Relations,”
- “The Principle of First Differences, and the Multiplication and Exponentiation of Relations,” and
- “Arithmetic of Relation-Numbers”;
- “General Theory of Series,”
- “On Sections, Segments, Stretches, and Derivatives,” and
- “On Convergence, and the Limits of Functions.”
- “Well-Ordered Series,”
- “Finite and Infinite Series and Ordinals,” and
- “Compact Series, Rational Series, and Continuous Series.”
- “Generalization of Number,”
- “Vector-Families,”
- “Measurement,” and
- “Cyclic Families.”
how much the work of logicians has done to make of English a language in which it is possible to think clearly and exactly on any subject. The Principia Mathematica are perhaps a greater contribution to our language than they are to mathematics. (1927, 291)
We have given proofs rather shortly in this Section, particularly in the case of purely arithmetical lemmas, of which the proofs are perfectly straightforward, but tedious if written out at length. (1913, 2nd edn 461)
Bibliography
- Blackwell, Kenneth, 2005, “A Bibliographical Index for Principia Mathematica,” Russell, 25: 77-80.
- –––, 2011, “The Wit and Humour of Principia Mathematica,” in Nicholas Griffin, Bernard Linsky and Kenneth Blackwell (2011) Principia Mathematica at 100, in Russell (Special Issue), 31(1): 151–160.
- Burgess, John P., 2005, “Fixing Frege,” Princeton: Princeton University Press.
- Chihara, Charles, 1973, Ontology and the Vicious Circle Principle, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
- Church, Alonzo, 1974, “Russellian Simple Type Theory,” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 47: 21–33.
- –––, 1978, “A Comparison of Russell's Resolution of the Semantical Antinomies with that of Tarski,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 41: 747–760; repr. in A.D. Irvine (ed.), Bertrand Russell: Critical Assessments, vol. 2, New York and London: Routledge, 1999, 96–112.
- Collins, Jordan E., 2012, A History of the Theory of Types: Developments after the Second Edition of Principia Mathematica, Saarbrücken: Lambert Academic Publishing.
- Copi, Irving, 1971, The Theory of Logical Types, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
- Eliot, T.S., 1927, “Commentary,” The Monthly Criterion, October 1927.
- Frege, Gottlob, 1893/1903, Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, Band I (1893), Band II (1903), Jena: Verlag Hermann Pohle; ed. and trans. by M. Furth in part as The Basic Laws of Arithmetic, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1964.
- Gabbay, Dov M., and John Woods (eds.), 2009, Handbook of the History of Logic: Volume 5 — Logic From Russell to Church, Amsterdam: Elsevier/North Holland.
- Gandon, Sébastien, 2008, “Which Arithmetization for which Logicism? Russell on Relations and Quantities in The Principles of Mathematics,” History and Philosophy of Logic, 29: 1–30.
- –––, 2011, “Principia Mathematica,” Logique et Analyse, 54: 225–247.
- –––, 2012, Russell's Unknown Logicism, New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
- Gödel, Kurt, 1944, “Russell's Mathematical Logic,” in Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell, 3rd edn, New York: Tudor, 1951, 123–153; repr. in Paul Benacerraf and Hilary Putnam (eds), Philosophy of Mathematics, 2nd edn, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983, 447–469; repr. in David F. Pears (ed.) (1972) Bertrand Russell: A Collection of Critical Essays, Garden City, New York: Anchor Books, 192–226; and repr. in A.D. Irvine (ed.) Bertrand Russell: Critical Assessments, vol. 2, New York and London: Routledge, 1999, 113–134.
- Grattan-Guinness, I., 2000, The Search for Mathematical Roots: 1870-1940, Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.
- Griffin, Nicholas, and Bernard Linsky (eds.), 2013, The Palgrave Centenary Companion to Principia Mathematica, London: Palgrave Macmillan.
- ––– and Kenneth Blackwell (eds.), 2011, Principia Mathematica at 100, Hamilton, ON: Bertrand Russell Research Centre; also published in Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies (Special Issue), 31(1).
- Guay, Alexandre (ed.), 2012, Autour de Principia Mathematica de Russell et Whitehead, Dijon: Editions Universitaires de Dijon.
- Hale, Bob, and Crispin Wright, 2001, The Reason's Proper Study, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Hintikka, Jaakko, 2009, “Logicism,” in A.D. Irvine (ed.), Philosophy of Mathematics, Amsterdam: Elsevier/North Holland, 271–290.
- Kanamori, Akihiro, 2009, “Set Theory from Cantor to Cohen,” in A.D. Irvine (ed.), Philosophy of Mathematics, Amsterdam: Elsevier/North Holland, 395-459.
- Landini, Gregory, 1998, Russell's Hidden Substitutional Theory, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 2011, Russell, London and New York: Routledge.
- Link, Godehard (ed.), 2004, One Hundred Years of Russell's Paradox, Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter.
- Linsky, Bernard, 1990, “Was the Axiom of Reducibility a Principle of Logic?” Russell, 10: 125–140; reprinted in A.D. Irvine (ed.) (1999) Bertrand Russell: Critical Assessments, 4 vols., London: Routledge, vol. 2, 150–264.
- –––, 1999, Russell's Metaphysical Logic, Stanford: CSLI Publications.
- –––, 2002, “The Resolution of Russell's Paradox in Principia Mathematica,” Philosophical Perspectives, 16: 395–417.
- –––, 2003, “Leon Chwistek on the No-Classes Theory in Principia Mathematica,” History and Philosophy of Logic, 25: 53–71.
- –––, 2011, The Evolution of Principia Mathematica: Bertrand Russell's Manuscripts and Notes for the Second Edition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- ––– and Kenneth Blackwell, 2006, “New Manuscript Leaves and the Printing of the First Edition of Principia Mathematica” Russell, 25: 141–154.
- Mares, Edwin, 2007, “The Fact Semantics for Ramified Type Theory and the Axiom of Reducibility” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 48: 237–251.
- Mayo-Wilson, Conor, 2011, “Russell on Logicism and Coherence,” in Nicholas Griffin, Bernard Linsky and Kenneth Blackwell (2011) Principia Mathematica at 100, in Russell(Special Issue), 31(1): 63–79.
- Mukhopadhyay, Arnab Kumar, Kumar Mitra and Sanjukta Basu (eds.), 2011, Revisiting Principia Mathematica after 100 Years, Kolkata, India: Gangchil.
- Murawski, Roman, 2011, “On Chwistek's Philosophy of Mathematics,” in Nicholas Griffin, Bernard Linsky and Kenneth Blackwell (2011) Principia Mathematica at 100, in Russell(Special Issue), 31(1): 121–130.
- Proops, Ian, 2006, “Russell's Reasons for Logicism,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 44: 267–292.
- Quine, W.V.O., 1960, Word and Object, Cambridge: MIT Press.
- –––, 1966a, Selected Logic Papers, New York: Random House.
- –––, 1966b, Ways of Paradox, New York: Random House.
- Ramsey, Frank P., 1931, The Foundations of Mathematics, London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner.
- Rodriguez-Consuegra, Francisco, 1991, The Mathematical Philosophy of Bertrand Russell, Boston: Birkhäuser Press; repr. 1993.
- Russell, Bertrand, 1903, The Principles of Mathematics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- –––, 1919, Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, London: George Allen & Unwin.
- –––, 1948, “Whitehead and Principia Mathematica,” Mind, 57: 137–138.
- –––, 1959, My Philosophical Development, London: George Allen and Unwin, and New York: Simon and Schuster; reprinted London: Routledge, 1993.
- –––, 1967, 1968, 1969, The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell, 3 vols., London: George Allen and Unwin; Boston: Little Brown and Company (Vols 1 and 2), New York: Simon and Schuster (Volume 3).
- Shapiro, Stewart (ed.), 2005, The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Stevens, Graham, 2011, “Logical Form in Principia Mathematica,” in Nicholas Griffin, Bernard Linsky and Kenneth Blackwell, Principia Mathematica at 100, in Russell(Special Issue), 31(1): 9-28.
- Urquhart, Alasdair, 1988, “Russell's Zig-Zag Path to the Ramified Theory of Types,” Russell, 8: 82–91.
- –––, 2012, Review of Bernard Linsky's The Evolution of Principia Mathematica: Bertrand Russell's Manuscripts and Notes for the Second Edition, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, [available online].
- Wahl, Russell, 2011, “The Axiom of Reducibility,” in Nicholas Griffin, Bernard Linsky and Kenneth Blackwell, Principia Mathematica at 100, in Russell (Special Issue), 31(1): 45-62.
- Whitehead, Alfred North, 1898, A Treatise on Universal Algebra, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- –––, 1906, “On Mathematical Concepts of the Material World,”, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London (Series A), 205: 465–525.
- –––, 1926, “Principia Mathematica”, Mind, 35: 130.
- ––– and Bertrand Russell, 1910, 1912, 1913, Principia Mathematica, 3 vols, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2nd edn, 1925 (Vol. 1), 1927 (Vols 2, 3); abridged as Principia Mathematica to *56, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1962. (Page numbers are to the second edition.)
- –––, Bertrand Russell, and M.R. James, 1910, Contract for the First Edition of Principia Mathematica, Russell, 31 (2011): 82.
- Wright, Crispin, 1983, Frege's Conception of Numbers as Objects, Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press.
Academic Tools
How to cite this entry. Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society. Look up this entry topic at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.
Other Internet Resources
- Principia Mathematica: Volume 1 (University of Michigan Historical Math Collection)
- Principia Mathematica: Volume 2 (University of Michigan Historical Math Collection)
- Principia Mathematica: Volume 3 (University of Michigan Historical Math Collection)
- Principia Mathematica: Whitehead and Russell (Stanley Burris, University of Waterloo)